Skip to content

23 September 2021

What is wrong with inequality?

We live at a time of very high inequality within many countries: these inequalities are found across the dimensions of income, wealth and the ownership of productive assets, educational opportunity, life expectancy, health and political influence. Across the developed world, many such inequalities have been growing since the 1970s, although at different rates in different countries (Piketty, 2014; Atkinson, 2015). At the same time, globally, our world has seen a tremendous decline in poverty: over the past 25 years, a billion people have been lifted out of extreme poverty. Today about 10% of the world lives in extreme poverty, defined as less than $1.90 per day; in 1990 that number was 37%. This has meant that inequality between countries has also somewhat declined at the same time that inequality within many individual countries has been increasing (Ravallion, 2018).

This rising inequality, particularly with respect to in-country economic inequality, is a growing concern of a number of contemporary social movements. The COVID-19 pandemic has underscored this concern. In the UK, it has disproportionately affected black people, those from other minority ethnic groups and those with disabilities (House of Commons Women and Equalities Committee, 2020; Oung and Elias, 2020). Underlying economic inequalities have strongly shaped individuals’ opportunities to work from home and to isolate when ill or at risk of spreading the virus.

However, some people argue that we should focus only on eliminating global and domestic poverty and not worry about inequality. Some also argue that greater equality always comes at a high cost: economist Arthur Okun claims that there is a trade-off between equality and efficiency (Okun, 1975); the philosopher Robert Nozick spoke for many critics when he charged that achieving distributional equality requires constant interference with people’s liberty (Nozick, 1974). Others have argued that equality is at odds with the value of ‘meritocracy’ since people have different and unequal talents (Mankiw, 2013). Finally, some critics go even further and contend that a concern with equality reflects a moral failing: it is rooted in envy or resentment of the better-off (Nietzsche, 1989 [1887]).

We will argue that all of these objections are mistaken or can be addressed. Inequality matters. At the same time, not all inequalities between people are objectionable or important. Some people are taller than others; some are better at hand–eye coordination, while others are better cooks; some excel at music while others are tone deaf; college professors are usually less fit than professional athletes. But these inequalities do not typically elicit moral concern. Any view about what is wrong with inequality has to deal with the pervasive fact of human difference and to distinguish those inequalities that matter from those that give no cause for concern.

This chapter lays out the reasons we have for objecting to certain differences between what individuals have and in how they relate to one another. Our aim is to show that there is a plurality of reasons to be concerned with such differences and not simply with the absolute amount that each individual has considered independently (Scanlon, 2018). Further, we argue against a limited focus on income inequality. Other forms of inequality can also matter.

Section 2 introduces some of the key concepts in the philosophical discussion of equality. Sections 3–5 then set out arguments for why inequality is objectionable and we should act to reduce it. Section 3 focuses on arguments that reducing inequalities can increase or maximise social welfare. Sections 4 and 5 focus on arguments that inequalities are unfair. Section 4 focuses on arguments that inequality can be unfair by virtue of what causes it, while Section 5 focuses on arguments that it can be unfair by virtue of its consequences. In Section 6, we then consider, and largely reject, some notable arguments against seeking to reduce inequality. Section 7 concludes.

Executive summary

  • We have reasons to reduce inequalities. Some argue that inequality is of no significance provided that everyone has ‘enough’ (the ‘sufficiency’ view). But there are numerous reasons why we should seek to reduce inequalities that go beyond the importance of achieving sufficiency.
  • Reasons to reduce inequalities include that measures to do so can enhance social welfare and that they can make society fairer. Inequalities can be unfair because of what causes them (e.g. discrimination or other failures of equality of opportunity) and/or because of their consequences (e.g. they cause objectionable inequalities in status or power). We have reason to remove unfair causes of inequalities and to prevent unfair consequences.
  • When acting to reduce inequalities an important guiding principle is that of social or relational equality. This includes equality of social status and an absence of domination.
  • To realise relational equality, egalitarian strategy should not only focus on income transfers, but consider a wider range of approaches including measures to spread the distribution of assets/wealth and to build associational power.
  • In acting to reduce inequalities at the national level it is necessary to respect global justice and environmental responsibilities.

Cite this as:

Satz, D. and White, S. (2021), ‘What is wrong with inequality?’, IFS Deaton Review of Inequalities, https://ifs.org.uk/inequality/what-is-wrong-with-inequality/